[ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]

assume compositionality, you can account for both systematicity and
productivity; and if you don t, you can t. Whether or not productivity and
systematicity prove that conceptual content is compositional, they are
clearly substantial straws in the wind. I find it persuasive that there are
continental drift explains why (e.g.) South America fits so nicely into Africa. It does so,
however, not by entailing that South America fits into Africa, but by providing a theoretical
background in which the fact that they fit comes, as it were, as no surprise. Similarly, mutatis
mutandis, for the explanation of systematicity by compositionality.
Inferences from systematicity to compositionality are  arguments to the best
explanation , and are (of course) non-demonstrative; which is (of course) not at all the same
as their being implausible or indecisive. Compare Cummins 1996, which appears to be
confused about this.
Chaps. 5 & 6 11/3/97 1:10 PM Page 99
Prototypes and Compositionality 99
quite a few such straws, and they appear all to be blowing in the same
direction.
The Best Argument for Compositionality
The best argument for the compositionality of mental (and linguistic)
representation is that its traces are ubiquitous; not just in very general
features of cognitive capacity like productivity and systematicity, but also
everywhere in its details. Deny productivity and systematicity if you will;
you still have these particularities to explain away.
Consider, for example: the availability of (definite) descriptions is surely
a universal property of natural languages. Descriptions are nice to have
because they make it possible to talk (mutatis mutandis, to think) about a
thing even if it isn t available for ostension and even if you don t know its
name; even, indeed, if it doesn t have a name (as with ever so many real
numbers). Descriptions can do this job because they pick out unnamed
individuals by reference to their properties. So, for example,  the brown
cow picks out a certain cow; viz. the brown one. It does so by referring to
a property, viz. being brown, which that cow has and no other cow does
that is contextually relevant. Things go wrong if (e.g.) there are no
contextually relevant cows; or if none of the contextually relevant cows is
brown; or if more than one of the contextually relevant cows is brown . . .
And so forth.
OK, but just how does all this work? Just what is it about the syntax and
semantics of descriptions that allows them to pick out unnamed
individuals by reference to their properties? Answer:
i. Descriptions are complex symbols which have terms that express
properties among their syntactic constituents;
and
ii. These terms contribute the properties that they express to determine
what the descriptions that contain them specify.
It s because  brown means brown that it s the brown cow that  the brown
cow picks out. Since you can rely on this arrangement, you can be
confident that  the brown cow will specify the local brown cow even if you
don t know which cow the local brown cow is; even if you don t know that
it s Bossie, for example, or that it s this cow. That, however, is just to say
that descriptions succeed in their job because they are compositional. If
English didn t let you use  brown context-independently to mean brown,
and  cow context-independently to mean cow, it couldn t let you use  the
brown cow to specify a brown cow without naming it.
Chaps. 5 & 6 11/3/97 1:10 PM Page 100
100 Prototypes and Compositionality
Names, by contrast, succeed in their job because they aren t
compositional; not even when they are syntactically complex. Consider
 the Iron Duke , to which  Iron does not contribute iron, and which you
can therefore use to specify the Iron Duke even if you don t know what he
was made of. Names are nicer than descriptions because you don t have to
know much to specify their bearers, although you do have to know what
their bearers are called. Descriptions are nicer than names because,
although you do have to know a lot to specify their bearers, you don t have
to know what their bearers are called. What s nicer than having the use of
either names or descriptions is having the use of both. I agree that, as a
piece of semantic theory, this is all entirely banal; but that s my point, so
don t complain. There is, to repeat, no need for fancy arguments that the
representational systems we talk and think in are in large part
compositional; you find the effects of their compositionality just about
wherever you look.
I must apologize for having gone on at such length about the arguments
pro and con conceptual compositionality; the reason I ve done so is that, [ Pobierz całość w formacie PDF ]

  • zanotowane.pl
  • doc.pisz.pl
  • pdf.pisz.pl
  • zsf.htw.pl